University of San Francisco School of Law Law Review, Vol. 58: Call for Submissions

0
27
Posted by Alejandra Chumbes, community karma 27
Vol. 58 is now accepting submissions for publication for our issue one. We are seeking to secure articles by the end of May, but we eagerly accept any submissions to publish for a subsequent issue. USF SOL Law Review welcomes articles from all areas of law.

The University of San Francisco Law Review is currently accepting article submissions for Volume 58 to be published in Fall 2023. Submissions in all legal fields will be considered.

Authors may submit their manuscripts and CVs/resumes through Scholastica; directly via email to: ee.usflrev@usfca.edu; or https://usfblogs.usfca.edu/lawreview/submit/. The deadline to submit articles is May 27, 2023. 

Thank you and we look forward to reviewing your submissions.  

1 Comment

0
19945
Charles Lamb, community karma 19945
Dear Ms. Chumbes,
I submitted the attached article, "The Supreme Court, Constitutional Development, and Evolution Theory: A Critique," to the University of San Francisco Law Review earlier through Scholastica. However, since you have just now asked for submissions, I send it to you again. My CV is attached at the end of this email.
Best,
Charles M. Lamb
Research Professor
University at Buffalo
State University of New York

 

Dear Articles Editor,

How are transformational changes in American constitutional law over time best understood and conceptualized? We explore this question in “The Supreme Court, Constitutional Development, and Evolution Theory: A Critique.” It primarily emphasizes University of Chicago Law School Professor David Strauss’s publications, how they present the early stages of a descriptive theory of constitutional interpretation and evolution, and how Strauss’s theoretical contributions could be strengthened. Highlighted here are ten milestone Supreme Court rulings with the objective of determining which were “evolutionary” as opposed to “modernizing,” based on Strauss’s theory. On various occasions the selected cases demonstrate how Strauss’s theory can be refined or broadened. The concluding section assesses Strauss’s contribution to the study of American constitutional evolution and how it can be revamped. There we argue that Strauss relies on concepts that should be clarified and polished, and he should make his theory more comprehensive. In addition, he should attempt the most difficult task of all: developing a causal theory of constitutional change. (Word Count: 12,965).

Best wishes,

 

Charles M. Lamb, Ph. D.

Research Professor

Department of Political Science

University at Buffalo, SUNY

Buffalo, NY 14260

clamb@buffalo.edu

 

 

 

 

 

 

THE SUPREME COURT, CONSTITUTIONAL DEVELOPMENT,

AND EVOLUTION THEORY: A CRITIQUE

 

Charles M. Lamb, Ph. D.

Research Professor

Department of Political Science

University at Buffalo, SUNY

Buffalo, NY 14260

clamb@buffalo.edu

 

Jacob R. Neiheisel, Ph.D.

Associate Professor

Department of Political Science

University at Buffalo, SUNY

Buffalo, NY 14260

jacobnei@buffalo.edu

 

 

Direct correspondence to Charles M. Lamb, Department of Political Science, University at Buffalo, Buffalo, NY 14260


 

Abstract

This article spotlights how University of Chicago Professor David Strauss’s publications present the early stages of a descriptive theory of constitutional interpretation and evolution, and how his theoretical contributions might be strengthened. Specifically highlighted here are ten milestone Supreme Court rulings with the objective of determining which were “evolutionary” as opposed to “modernizing,” based on Strauss’s theoretical formulations. On various occasions these cases demonstrate how Strauss’s theory can be not only refined but broadened. The concluding section assesses Strauss’s contribution to the study of American constitutional development and how it might be revamped. There we argue that despite Strauss’s influence on the study of the Supreme Court and constitutional evolution, he relies on concepts that must be clarified and honed for future research, and he must make his theory more comprehensive. At a minimum, Strauss should extend his descriptive theory to three types of Supreme Court decisions: those that are retrogressive, revolutionary, and confirming status quo in nature. Finally, Strauss should attempt the most difficult task of all: developing a causal theory of constitutional change.

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

Table of Contents

 

I.

Introduction

5

II.

Building on McCloskey

6

III.

Theoretical Fundamentals

9

IV.

Bolling v. Sharpe

13

V.

Gideon v. Wainwright

15

VI.

Reynolds v. Sims

18

VII.

Katz v. United States

21

VIII.

New York Times v. United States

25

IX.

Cruzan v. Director, Missouri Department of Health

27

X.

United States v. Virginia

29

XI.

Lawrence v. Texas

31

XII.

Obergefell v. Hodges

35

XIII.

Bostock v. Clayton County

37

XIV.

Revising Evolution Theory

39


 

I.                   Introduction

The United States Supreme Court’s constitutional decisions have changed in extraordinary ways throughout American history. Only recently the Roberts Court handed down several important rulings that surprised observers with how much the new conservative majority departed from precedent.[1] Most notably, the Court reversed Roe v. Wade[2] in Dobbs v. Jackson Women’s Health Organization,[3] abandoning a fundamental constitutional right recognized by the Court for almost five decades. Yet while students of the Court meticulously study specific constitutional developments such as these from term-to-term, they must also keep in mind the larger picture: how transformational changes in constitutional law over time can best be understood and conceptualized. For this reason, we begin with the scholarship of Robert McCloskey, a Harvard political scientist and constitutional historian, as he presented the basic theory of major constitutional eras in his book, The American Supreme Court.[4] Then given McCloskey’s theoretical foundation, our focus shifts to David Strauss of the University of Chicago Law School and his contribution to understanding constitutional development and evolution in the United States.

McCloskey envisioned the Supreme Court's history as consisting of three great constitutional periods, each lasting for decades and each characterized by critical political and legal issues. The first era spanned the period from the Constitution’s ratification until the Civil War, when the nation faced repeated political collisions between those who favored nationalism and those who preferred states’ rights. During this developmental epoch, the High Court endorsed and broadly construed the powers of the federal government under the new Constitution.[5] The second constitutional era, covering from the end of the Civil War to 1937, triggered momentous changes in the Court's work. Its focus went primarily from nation-state relations to the legal and political battle over how much government could regulate economic activity as America transitioned from an agricultural to an industrial economy. The second constitutional era was a period in which the Court shielded business from government control through its interpretation of economic liberty.[6] The third constitutional era, which McCloskey described as the civil rights era, began in 1937, as the Court once more changed policy directions and ultimately allowed extensive government regulation of business and the nation’s economy. Previous problems associated with slavery now turned into a concern over the rights of African Americans and civil rights and liberties more generally. During the civil rights era the Court applied almost all the provisions of the Bill of Rights to the states and expanded the rights of racial, religious, political, and sexual minorities as well as the rights of criminal suspects and defendants.[7] In addition to his descriptive theory of three major constitutional eras, McCloskey proposed a causal theory of constitutional development, but we will wait until the concluding section to introduce it since Strauss has yet to attempt the same feat. 

II.                Building on McCloskey

This article focuses on a topic central to the work of both McCloskey and Strauss: leading Supreme Court rulings during the civil rights era and how they should be interpreted in terms of constitutional evolution and development. Since McCloskey’s The American Supreme Court was published, except for originalist interpretations,[8] only one other major school of thought has survived on constitutional change. However, it goes by different names, which can be confusing depending on how they are used. The two most popular current theoretical characterizations of constitutional development are emphasized here.

First, many scholars—and some Supreme Court justices—have described the Court’s decisions in terms of a “living Constitution.”[9] This concept suggests that the Constitution has been and should be interpreted to adapt to meet changing legal, political, economic, and social problems—an idea inherent in McCloskey’s vision of constitutional history. As Chief Justice Marshall famously wrote in McCulloch v. Maryland,[10] “we must never forget that it is a constitution we are expounding,” and constitutions are made up of broad principles intended to “endure for ages to come, and consequently, be adapted to the various crises of human affairs.”[11] Thus, for instance, even though the Constitution is written in unequivocal language with respect to some individual rights, such as “Congress shall make no law . . . abridging the freedom of speech, or of the press . . . ,” (emphasis added), the Court has frequently relied on Marshall’s wisdom and decided accordingly in scores of famous cases.  

Second, some scholars contend that certain Supreme Court rulings represent “constitutional evolution.” The same scholars even refer to the notion of a living Constitution in their writing but go beyond it to emphasize the concept of evolution.[12] Constitutional evolution is also intrinsic in Robert McCloskey’s three constitutional eras framework, but probably the leading proponent of constitutional evolution today is David Strauss. Strauss has repeatedly depended on the idea of evolution, and its conceptual cousin, “constitutional modernization,” to describe leading Supreme Court rulings during the civil rights era.[13] In relying on constitutional evolution, Strauss has been joined by Geoffrey Stone, also of the University of Chicago Law School, in their book, Democracy and Equality,[14] as explained below.

This article emphasizes Professor Strauss’s publications, how they present the early stages of a descriptive theory of constitutional interpretation and evolution, and how Strauss’s theoretical contributions might be strengthened. Specifically highlighted here are ten milestone Supreme Court rulings with the objective of determining which were “evolutionary” as opposed to “modernizing,” based on Strauss’s theoretical formulations. On numerous occasions the selected cases demonstrate how Strauss’s theory can be refined in some ways yet broadened in others. The concluding section assesses Strauss’s contribution to the study of American constitutional evolution and how it can be revamped for future research. There, we argue that, despite Strauss’s considerable influence on the study of the Supreme Court decision-making and constitutional evolution, he relies on concepts that need to be clarified and polished. He should likewise make his theory more comprehensive, at a minimum extending it to three possible types of Supreme Court decisions: those that are retrogressive, revolutionary, and confirming status quo in nature. In addition to refining his descriptive theory of constitutional interpretation and evolution, Strauss should attempt the most difficult task of all: developing a causal theory of constitutional change that surpasses the elementary one of McCloskey, as discussed in the final section of this article.

III.             Theoretical Fundamentals

McCloskey’s theory of major constitutional eras and what causes the Supreme Court to move from one great era to the next is far broader than Professor Strauss’s theory, which principally accentuates two concepts. First, constitutional development is evolutionary.[15] At its core, Strauss’s concept of evolution indicates that certain Supreme Court rulings depart from or extend common law in a way that significantly affects fundamental doctrines in constitutional law for relatively long periods of time. Evolutionary decisions are not determined by the Constitution’s text, according to Strauss; instead, they result from the Supreme Court’s need to articulate somewhat different or entirely new breakthrough policies to meet the demands of an everchanging legal, political, economic, and social world.[16]

One would anticipate that evolutionary constitutional change occurred following blockbuster Warren Court holdings like Brown v. Board of Education,[17] Mapp v. Ohio,[18] Griswold v. Connecticut,[19] and Miranda v. Arizona,[20] although some—especially Brown—have had more of an effect on constitutional law than on real-world America. Strauss has described historical instances of constitutional evolution by using the following illustrations: “clear and present danger; reckless disregard of the truth; separation of church and state; the presumption of innocence; proof of guilt beyond a reasonable doubt; the Miranda warnings; the unlawfulness of race and gender discrimination—these legal concepts . . . are not in the text” of the Constitution.[21] Rather, these and many other key constitutional doctrines have evolved because of leading Supreme Court decisions. Strauss addressed this theme in another article when he argued that his evolutionary theory generally embraced the idea that many fundamental developments have occurred in various areas of constitutional law without the Constitution being amended. Early examples include “the Marshall Court's consolidation of the role of the federal government; the decline of property qualifications for voting and the Jacksonian ascendance of popular democracy and political parties; the Taney Court's partial restoration of state sovereignty; the unparalleled changes wrought by the Civil War; . . . [and] the rise and fall of a constitutional freedom of contract.” More recent illustrations include “the great twentieth-century growth in the power of the executive (especially in foreign affairs) and the federal government generally; the civil rights era that began in the mid-twentieth century; the reformation of the criminal justice system during the same decades; and the movement toward gender equality in the last few decades.[22]

Strauss also asserts that the Supreme Court’s incorporation of the Bill of Rights vis-à-vis the states was unmistakably an evolutionary development.[23] As a result, unlike in the early 1920s, nearly all constitutional principles of justice and fairness that initially forbade federal intrusions on individual rights now constrain state and local governmental action. Numerous Court holdings may have had evolutionary effects on American democracy, based on Strauss’s theory, yet most did not dramatically influence the path of constitutional rights and liberties in the long run. However, Strauss has never provided a comprehensive list of evolutionary Supreme Court rulings; he has only asserted in different publications that certain decisions were evolutionary in nature. Otherwise, the reader must cull through his work, objectively interpret it, determine what is and is not an evolutionary decision, and leave with a sense of which rulings deserve to be on that list and why.

Second, Strauss relies on the concept of constitutional modernization, especially in his article, “The Modernizing Mission of Judicial Review.”[24] He has acknowledged that even though modernization through the use of judicial review has not been apparent in all areas of constitutional law, it has been the “dominant approach” in some key issues, including gender discrimination, cruel and unusual punishment, in addition to “the Commerce Clause, the religion clauses, constitutional criminal procedure, and other aspects of the Equal Protection Clause.”[25]

Take the example of cruel and unusual punishment, which Strauss has maintained is a textbook illustration of constitutional modernization. By invoking the concept of a modernizing approach to judicial review, Strauss means “an approach that, more or less consciously, looks to the future, not the past; that tries to bring laws up to date, rather than deferring to traditions; and that anticipates and accommodates, rather than limits, developments in popular opinion.”[26] After defining this concept, he shows how modernization was evident in a series of Eighth Amendment decisions extending from Weems v. United States,[27] through more recent rulings. In Weems, the Court held that the Cruel and Unusual Punishment Clause “’is not fastened to the obsolete, but may acquire meaning as public opinion becomes enlightened by a humane justice’ and that the Clause should be interpreted to enforce ‘the evolving standards of decency that mark the progress of a maturing society,’”[28] Strauss explained. “These formulations, with their emphasis on evolution, enlightenment, and progress, are almost an explicit statement of the modernizing approach.”[29] Here is a possibly redundant aspect in Strauss’s theory, as some cruel and unusual punishment cases exhibit both constitutional evolution and modernization. Are these concepts separate and distinct? Should a theory composed of two concepts at least contain two clearly distinguishable ideas? We will return to this point in the concluding section.

IV.              Bolling v. Sharpe[30]

With constitutional evolution and modernization in mind, we turn to ten eminent Supreme Court rulings from the civil rights era to see how Strauss has applied his theory, starting with Bolling v. Sharpe. In Brown,[31] writing for a unanimous Court, Chief Justice Warren declared that segregated schools inherently violated the Fourteenth Amendment’s Equal Protection Clause. Bolling was announced the same day. In contrast to Brown, Warren’s unanimous opinion in Bolling was based on an evolutionary interpretation of the Fifth Amendment and the Court’s precedents in Sweatt v. Painter[32] and McLaurin v. Oklahoma State Regents.[33] As Strauss has observed, “the text of the Constitution did not dictate Bolling, to say the least; Brown did. This certainly seems to be one unmistakable example of how the unwritten Constitution works in our system.”[34] Put otherwise, Bolling is “a case study of how a constitutional principle with a very weak grounding in the text not only can be adopted but can become unquestioned and extended.”[35]

Factually, in Bolling, Congress had passed a law segregating public schools in the District of Columbia but, of course, the Fourteenth Amendment’s Equal Protection Clause applies only to the states. Warren thus inserted what was necessary into the Constitution’s text by reading an “equal protection component” into the Due Process Clause of the Fifth Amendment, thereby requiring that Washington, DC, public schools be desegregated like state public schools. As Strauss has noted, that interpretation was not what the Fifth Amendment’s framers had in mind, meaning that Warren’s “conclusion would have to rely on evolutionary understandings and judgments of fairness and policy, rather than on the text alone.”[36] Moreover, “the subsequent uncritical acceptance of the ‘equal protection component’ of the Fifth Amendment is even more dramatic. . . . But the way Bolling’s principle so easily became a fixture, despite its very dubious textual basis, is pretty striking.”[37]

How did Warren explain his ruling in Bolling? He initially acknowledged the distinction between the Due Process and Equal Protection Clauses but observed that they are based on American notions of fairness and that they “are not mutually exclusive. The ‘equal protection of the laws’ is a more explicit safeguard of prohibited unfairness than ‘due process of the law,’ and therefore we do not imply that the two are always interchangeable phrases.”[38] Yet, Warren insisted, “discrimination may be so unjustifiable as to be violative of due process,”[39] so the liberty provision of the Fifth Amendment could be used to prohibit racial discrimination in Bolling. And how are we to know when a particular type of discrimination is that unjustifiable? “Liberty under law extends to the full range of conduct which the individual is free to pursue, and it cannot be restricted except for a proper governmental objective.”[40] Because public school segregation could never be a proper governmental objective after Brown, Congress’s statute must fall.

Strauss contends that changing political, legal, and social circumstances required the Bolling Court to read into the Constitution a principle that was imperative but not there, demonstrating how a liberal High Court can play a critical leadership role in American democracy when the legislative and executive branches cannot or will not act. Thus, according to Strauss, Brown and Bolling both support his evolutionary theory; the Supreme Court moved from a notoriously conservative position in Plessy v. Ferguson[41] to a more liberal position in the 1950s, announcing that meaningful change was expected with respect to school segregation in all states as well as the District of Columbia.

V.                 Gideon v. Wainwright[42]

Clarence Gideon, a white indigent drifter, was accused of breaking and entering a poolhall, a felony in Florida. Claiming his innocence but without money for a lawyer, Gideon requested assistance of counsel from a Florida court, but his request was denied. Gideon was convicted, sentenced to five years in prison, but petitioned the Supreme Court in a famous hand-written plea, which ultimately led to a unanimous ruling in his favor.[43]

Delivering the Court’s opinion in Gideon, Justice Black initially explained the controlling precedent, Betts v. Brady.[44] Betts was arrested for robbery in Maryland but was unable to afford counsel, so he asked that an attorney be appointed for him. The state judge responded that Maryland only appointed counsel where murder and rape were at issue.[45] At the Supreme Court, Justice Roberts’s 6-3 majority opinion announced that the Fourteenth Amendment’s Due Process Clause did not require that a state furnish counsel for a person tried for a noncapital criminal offense except under certain special circumstances. “That which may, in one setting, constitute a denial of fundamental fairness, shocking to the universal sense of justice, may, in other circumstances and in the light of other considerations, fall short of such denial.”[46] Roberts noted that in Powell v. Alabama,[47] the Court overruled the state death convictions of nine young, indigent African Americans accused of rape, because court-appointed counsel had not effectively represented them, thereby denying them of a fair trial. However, since Maryland required that counsel only be appointed in capital—not noncapital—cases, Roberts ruled that the state court had not denied Betts of due process; his trial had been fair.[48] Roberts also noted that in Johnson v. Zerbst[49] the Court interpreted the Sixth Amendment to require appointment of counsel in all federal cases involving indigents. Nonetheless, in a large percentage of states, the people and their courts did not view the appointment of counsel as a fundamental right essential to a fair trial.[50] Thus, in Betts, the Court chose not to incorporate the right to counsel against the states. Black, who dissented in Betts, argued in Gideon that Betts was wrongly decided as it broke from precedent indicating that criminal suspects cannot receive a fair trial unless counsel is appointed for them. As Black famously remarked, “lawyers in criminal courts are necessities, not luxuries.”[51] Even well-educated citizens often lack the skills needed to defend themselves. Accordingly, the Court overruled Betts and required that counsel be provided free to indigents in all noncapital criminal cases.

Stone and Strauss view Gideon as a groundbreaking evolutionary decision. “Gideon, like many Warren Court decisions expanding the rights of criminal defendants, had its roots in a dark chapter of American history,” they write. “Between the two world wars, ‘southern criminal cases . . . revealed Jim Crow at its worst.”[52] Many southern Blacks, if impoverished and poorly educated, found it extremely difficult to effectively defend themselves when accused of a crime. Gradually, evolutionary Supreme Court decisions sought to correct these and other right to counsel problems, beginning with Powell, and continuing with Zerbst and Gideon. According to Stone and Strauss, however, the Sixth Amendment’s original understanding did not include the idea that government should pay for an indigent defendant’s attorney. In their words, “Gideon was not the product of a single decision by the framers but lessons learned over a period of years, beginning with Powell—the kind of evolutionary development of precedent that is characteristic of constitutional law. Gideon, in this respect, resembles Brown and other Warren Court cases”[53] Indeed, “many of the Warren Court’s most important decisions, like Brown and Gideon, were not bolts from the blue. They built on what had gone before, in keeping with the evolutionary, precedent-based traditions of constitutional law.”[54]

VI.              Reynolds v. Sims[55]

The Warren Court’s “reapportionment revolution” was critical to the development of civil rights in America, and Reynolds v. Sims illustrates why. The Alabama state legislature was generally apportioned based on population during the 1960s, but each county was given a minimum of one representative, and the state’s legislative district lines had not been redrawn since 1900. As cities and towns grew, rural counties were drastically overrepresented in the state House of Representatives, and the state Senate was malapportioned as well. Urban voters tested the constitutionality of this malapportionment, and a federal district court ruled that Alabama’s apportionment scheme was unconstitutional based on Baker v. Carr.[56] The Supreme Court granted an appeal, ruling that the election of members of both houses of the state legislature must be based on the principle of one-person-one-vote to comply with the Equal Protection Clause.

Warren’s 8–1 majority opinion in Reynolds emphasized that voting is a fundamental constitutional right.[57] In addition, “legislators represent people, not trees or acres,” so vote dilution that occurs when rural areas are overrepresented is a form of discrimination in violation of equal protection. “To conclude differently,” Warren warned, “would appear to deny majority rights in a way that far surpasses any possible denial of minority rights that might otherwise be thought to result.”[58] The seats in both houses of state legislatures must therefore be based on population, unlike Congress. Guaranteeing that each state had an equal number of seats in the U.S. Senate was essential during the Constitutional Convention to avoid quarrels between the larger and smaller states, but that federal analogy was not applicable to state legislatures.[59] Unlike the original states, political subdivisions within the states were never sovereign, and thus the federal analogy was not apropos. Finally, Warren directed all states to “make an honest and good faith effort to construct districts, in both houses of its legislature, as nearly to equal population as is practicable.”[60]

If some Supreme Court decisions are evolutionary, could a small number be theoretically characterized as “revolutionary”? And, if so, does Reynolds qualify as a revolutionary ruling? In their book, Democracy and Equality, Stone and Strauss initially submit that Reynolds was revolutionary in nature. “Judged by many conventional criteria, the holding of Reynolds was very hard to defend. Judicial precedent did not support it; Colegrove [v. Green], decided not long before, was antithetical to Reynolds.[61] Moreover, “’one person, one vote’ has no obvious basis in the text of the Constitution.”[62] Stone and Strauss then pushed their assertion further: “The overall structure of the Constitution—which allows states to control voting, subject to specific nondiscrimination requirements that are provided in constitutional amendments—implies that the Court has no power to impose additional limits on the states’ prerogatives,” they wrote. “Even if the Court was justified in taking some steps to deal with malapportionment, the strict rule of population equality seemed to come out of nowhere.”[63] Finally, “Reynolds required virtually every state in the Union to revamp its central government institutions. In that way, it flouted principles of federalism and judicial restraint to an unprecedented degree.”[64]

This sounds like a persuasive argument that Reynolds was a revolutionary ruling, as a leading part of the Warren Court’s “reapportionment revolution.” Yet Stone and Strauss promptly make a different claim: that it was an evolutionary decision, or at least an influential piece of an evolutionary process. Reynolds, they say, “had foundations in American constitutional traditions, and it reflected a deep understanding of the Supreme Court’s role in a democracy. American history is characterized by the evolution toward equality in voting rights,”[65] and Reynolds was a vital step in that development. As part of the evolutionary process, property qualifications for voting were eliminated; the Fifteenth Amendment guaranteed the right to vote irrespective of race, color, or previous condition of servitude; the Seventeenth Amendment stipulated that U.S. senators would be popularly elected; and the Nineteenth Amendment declared that women had the right to vote. In other words, Reynolds “was not inevitable, and was not compelled by history. But it was a logical next step that had secure roots in those long-standing American traditions.”[66]

The differences in the first and second arguments suggest that the concepts of evolutionary and revolutionary Supreme Court decisions may be too malleable to be of general use. Where does one draw the line between the two? Nowadays, constitutional scholars can interpret them in various ways, as they wish. Although this is what legal minds are trained to do, this approach can present obvious problems from a social science perspective, as alluded to in the concluding section. Greater concept clarification and refinement are needed in the future if both concepts are to be adopted.

VII.           Katz v. United States[67]

Katz v. United States overruled Olmstead v. United States[68] and established a new privacy standard under the Fourth Amendment. In Olmstead, the Taft Court faced the question of whether the Fourth Amendment allowed federal law enforcement officials to use telephone wiretaps to secure incriminating evidence in a criminal case, without a search warrant, and whether that evidence was admissible at trial.[69] Chief Justice Taft persuaded four other justices to answer both questions in the affirmative. Taft maintained that the Fourth Amendment’s purpose was to protect against unreasonable searches and seizures of tangible or material things.[70] As a consequence, the Fourth Amendment was not abridged in Olmstead because no search and seizure of "persons, houses, papers, and effects" occurred; instead, only the sense of hearing was used by federal prohibition officers to obtain evidence.[71]

Fast forward to Katz. Charles Katz, a gambler, was under surveillance by the FBI, which tapped a public telephone booth where Katz made a call, providing evidence of bet-making from a public phone in violation of federal law.[72] Katz claimed that the evidence was inadmissible under the Fourth Amendment because FBI agents bugged the phone booth without obtaining a search warrant, but Olmstead had held that the use of electronic eavesdropping devices did not intrude upon Katz’s constitutional rights. Katz lost in the lower federal courts, but his attorney asked the Warren Court to rule that a public telephone booth is a constitutionally protected area.

Justice Stewart's 7–1 opinion for the Katz Court went beyond that concept, though, emphasizing that the "Fourth Amendment protects people, not places. What a person knowingly exposes to the public, even in his home or office, is not a subject of Fourth Amendment protection,” Stewart reasoned, “but what he seeks to preserve as private, even in an area assessable to the public, may be constitutionally protected.”[73] Based on this reasoning, Katz retained his right not to be overheard even though he used a public phone booth, and a telephone conversation is a thing that can be illegally seized given the Fourth Amendment. Under Olmstead and Goldman v. United States,[74] the Fourth Amendment limited only searches and seizures of tangible property, but now the Warren Court concluded that something intangible—like a phone call—was subject to constitutional protection, thereby overruling Olmstead and Goldman. Katz had a right to believe that his privacy would be protected while using a public phone booth, so this case constituted a search and seizure.[75]

Stone and Strauss believe that Katz “exemplifies” the notion of a living Constitution and constitutional evolution.[76] “The Warren Court’s embrace of the ‘Living Constitution’ approach,” they write, “rests on the premise that the framers of our Constitution sought to address the specific challenges facing the nation during their life-times, but also to establish fundamental principles that would sustain and guide our nation into an uncertain and evolving future.”[77] Those who advocate the concept of evolutionary development “maintain that the framers understood they were entrusting future generations with the responsibility to draw upon their experience in an ever-changing world to give concrete meaning to these broad principles over time.”[78] What is more, “under this approach, the principles enshrined in the Constitution do not change, but the application of those principles evolves as society changes, as technology changes, and as experience informs our understanding.”[79] As a result, Katz stands for the idea that “wiretapping a telephone call is functionally indistinguishable from opening someone’s mail,” and “the meaning of the word ‘search’ must evolve over time if the Constitution is truly to fulfill the fundamental purposes and intentions of the framers.”[80]

The difficulty with this account of Katz is twofold. First, it uses the concepts of constitutional evolution and a living Constitution interchangeably. If they are intended to be synonymous, that should be made clear at the outset, and it is not. That is, these two concepts are not systematically employed in some of Strauss’s writings. Indeed, throughout his book, The Living Constitution,[81] the concept of evolutionary development is frequently used, with no clear explanation of exactly what it means or how it differs from the notion of a living Constitution. Having two different characterizations of the same concept, and employing one alongside the other, muddies what is essential: the theoretical as well as the substantive conclusions being communicated to the reader. Second, this assessment of Katz emphasizes the intent of the framers, whereas Strauss’s other accounts of evolution often fail to allude to either the framers or their intent. Indeed, if Strauss mentions the framers in the context of constitutional evolution, it is frequently to say that their intent is either not ascertainable, or that its intent was not what the Court claimed it was in a particular case. And why is the framers’ intent relevant to describe constitutional evolution in Katz when the framers could not have foreseen the technological advances that allowed the police to tap the phone booth in Katz’s case in the first place, not to speak of the more advanced technology involved in later rulings like White v. United States,[82] California v. Ciraolo,[83] Kyllo v. United States,[84] and United States v. Jones?[85]

VIII.        New York Times v. United States[86]

In the Pentagon Papers case, the New York Times and the Washington Post had published articles in 1971 based on top secret government documents given to them by Pentagon official Daniel Ellsberg, recounting the history of the Vietnam War. The federal government sued the newspapers, asking a federal district court to issue a temporary restraining order to prevent the publication of other articles. The government, speaking for President Nixon, contended that the articles’ publication would cause irreparable injury to national security while the newspapers insisted that the material was largely of historical interest.[87] Eighteen days after the suit was filed in district court, a per curiam decision was handed down by the Burger Court in record time.[88] The 6–3 Court stressed that the federal government had a very heavy burden of proof to justify prior restraint. If it failed to meet that burden, the Times must be allowed to publish these documents, even though they were classified; after that, the government could file suit against the Times if it believed the newspaper had breached federal law.[89]

Although the Court’s conclusions in New York Times were historic, the concurring opinions stand out in terms of constitutional interpretation. Justice Black claimed that the First Amendment was violated each moment that the Times was restrained. The press “must be free to publish news, whatever the source, without censorship, injunctions, or prior restraints.”[90] Besides, Black declared, the president had no inherent power to stop a newspaper from publishing, even where national security was implicated.[91] Justice Douglas contended that the First Amendment was designed to prohibit government suppression of embarrassing information.[92] “Secrecy in government is fundamentally anti-democratic, perpetuating bureaucratic errors,” he explained. “Open debate and discussion of public issues are vital to our national health.”[93] Justice Brennan also concurred, stressing that the First Amendment stood as an absolute bar to prior judicial restraints under these circumstances.[94]

What does Strauss say about New York Times and either constitutional evolution or modernization?[95] He sees the former concept as solely applicable here. Most members of the Times Court recognized “that prior restraints are anathema to a system of freedom of expression. To that extent, the Pentagon Papers decision can be traced to the intentions of the framers.”[96] But this connection to evolution is not the only one that Strauss perceived. The imperative need to protect political speech, even if it has negative consequences for government, is the “central theme [that] emerged from the evolutionary process that is characteristic of our living Constitution.”[97] More specifically, our freedom of expression law is “the product of common law evolution,” Strauss declared. “It developed over time, fitfully, by a process in which principles and standards were tried and sometimes eventually accepted, sometimes abandoned, sometimes modified, in light of experience and an ongoing, explicit assessment of whether they were sound as a matter of policy.”[98] In the end, Strauss wrote, “the law of the First Amendment is a creation of the living Constitution.”[99] Hence, as with Katz, Strauss’s evaluation of the Pentagon Papers case uses constitutional evolution and a living Constitution interchangeably.

IX.              Cruzan v. Director, Missouri Department of Health[100]

A remarkable case was argued before the Rehnquist Court on December 6, 1989. At the center of the case was twenty-five-year-old Nancy Beth Cruzan, who was thrown clear from her car in an automobile accident that took place in Missouri in 1983, leaving her in a permanent vegetative state. Although she could possibly live for another thirty years, permanent brain damage meant that Cruzan would forever be unconscious, with no ability to take food or liquid, and without any memory or any way to ever communicate with others.[101] Cruzan’s parents initially approved of feeding tubes to keep their daughter alive even though a former housemate had testified at trial that Cruzan said, one year before her accident, that she would rather die than live in a vegetative state.[102] However, after four years Cruzan’s parents requested that the feeding tubes be removed so she could die, hospital officials refused without a court order, and a state court subsequently found that Cruzan had a fundamental constitutional right to refuse treatment that prolonged her death. The Missouri Supreme Court denied that such a right existed.[103]

Chief Justice Rehnquist self-assigned the 5–4 opinion for the Court in Cruzan, holding that a state may require that evidence of an incompetent patient's wishes for the withdrawal of life-prolonging treatment must be clearly and convincingly proven.[104] Rehnquist steadfastly asserted that, here, individual rights under the liberty provision of the Due Process Clause did not outweigh the state’s interest in protecting and preserving human life.[105] Missouri law required clear and convincing evidence that an incompetent person wanted to withdraw life-prolonging treatment so that he or she might die and, again, the trial court testimony of a housemate indicated that Cruzan had declared that she did not want to exist in a permanent vegetative state.[106] Rehnquist nevertheless underscored that states obviously have an interest in preserving life and for that reason prohibited homicide and suicide. Aside from that, in litigation such as this, the state was justified in requiring high standards of proof, as a person's life is at stake and there is no room for error. It was conceivable, for instance, that family members might not act to protect a patient. Here, then, Missouri was justified in requiring clear and convincing proof of that, and no such evidence was presented here.[107]

Strauss has said little about Cruzan in his published work, probably because he feels it represents neither constitutional evolution nor modernization. Still, this milestone case is included in this article for a reason. As indicated in the concluding section, Cruzan is a status quo confirming decision—a key point to keep in mind if we are to build upon and strengthen Strauss’s theory of American constitutional development.

X.                 United States v. Virginia[108]

A vital issue pertaining to women’s equal educational opportunity was presented to the Rehnquist Court in United States v. Virginia. Virginia had a long tradition of providing military training for men at the Virginia Military Institute (VMI), with VMI’s training designed to produce citizens and soldiers for leadership positions. The Department of Justice (DOJ) filed suit against Virginia, claiming that VMI’s exclusion of women denied them equal protection. On the advice of a court of appeals ruling, Virginia then created a parallel program for women, known as the Virginia Women’s Institute for Leadership (VWIL) at Mary Baldwin College; however, the VWIL did not use the same military methods as VMI and was not equal to VMI in various tangible or intangible aspects of education. The lower courts sustained the female alternative to VMI, and DOJ appealed.[109]

Justice Ginsburg, widely known as a women’s rights advocate, wrote for a 7–1 majority holding that Virginia defied the requirements of equal protection by excluding women from educational opportunities provided to men at an all-male military school if female applicants were capable of all the individual activities required of male cadets.[110] In addition, the parallel program for women in this case failed to provide equal tangible and intangible aspects of education and, therefore, did not provide an acceptable remedy for the Equal Protection Clause violation.[111] Ginsburg initially surveyed the nation’s history of sex discrimination and related Supreme Court decisions. She highlighted that, according to Mississippi University for Women v. Hogan,[112] a state may avoid an Equal Protection Clause violation by demonstrating that a challenged legal classification based on gender served important governmental objectives and that the discriminatory means employed were substantially related to the achievement of those objectives.

After emphasizing that a state’s justification must be exceptionally convincing, Ginsburg concluded that Virginia presented no such justification for prohibiting women from attending VMI and that the remedy was inadequate to rectify the constitutional infringement. Although Virginia advanced two defenses for the challenged legal classification—that single-sex education contributed to diversity in educational approaches and that VMI’s unique educational mold would need to be changed if women were admitted—Ginsburg found no support for these justifications given this infraction of the Equal Protection Clause.[113] Historically, diversity was not a goal of Virginia’s support of the all-male academy, and the constitutional infringement here outweighed the significance of any changes that must be made in VMI’s educational approach.[114] VWIL was inferior to VMI in both terms of tangible and intangible aspects of education and was not an acceptable remedy for the constitutional violation that occurred here.

Strauss’s treatment of Virginia has been straightforward: it was a modernizing decision as well as the Court’s “most important” sex discrimination ruling until that time.[115] The Court’s use of modernization was appropriate in Virginia, Strauss wrote, because women were excluded from VMI “in an era when attitudes were so different from what they are today.”[116] Perhaps, he noted, the issue could have been “whether a classification is in fact justified, not whether the people who adopted it had good reasons,” but modernization required something quite different: that “a policy truly reflects a present-day political decision, made according to present-day ideas about women’s role in society and the economy.”[117]

XI.             Lawrence v. Texas[118]

Harris County, Texas, police caught John Lawrence and Tyrone Garner engaged in sodomy in 1998, in violation of a Texas law prohibiting homosexual conduct. Both Lawrence and Garner were found guilty of “deviant homosexual conduct” under this law and fined $200.[119] On appeal, a Texas court of appeals sustained the state’s homosexual conduct statute.[120]

Given this backdrop, Justice Kennedy—who also wrote the Court’s opinions in Romer v. Evans,[121] United States v. Windsor,[122] and Obergefell v. Hodges[123]began Lawrence by addressing one of the most venerated concepts of democracy: liberty. Liberty “presumes an autonomy of self that includes freedom of thought, belief, expression, and certain intimate conduct.”[124] Therefore, the question in Lawrence was whether the notion of liberty in the Due Process Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment allowed a state to make intimate sexual conduct between people of the same sex a crime. Kennedy replied in the negative; government may not infringe on this critical aspect of liberty.[125]

Griswold[126] was the most relevant constitutional point of departure for Lawrence, according to Kennedy, although there were obvious differences in the two rulings.[127] Griswold addressed the fundamental right of intimate relations between a husband and wife, and Justice Douglas’s constitutional reasoning in Griswold recognized the right to marital sexual privacy as a peripheral First Amendment right—that is, “the First Amendment has a penumbra where privacy is protected from government intrusion, much as it is under the right to association cases.”[128] But Lawrence and Garner were not married, so where could Kennedy’s constitutional reasoning in Lawrence go from there? His response featured two prominent precedents: Eisenstadt v. Baird,[129] which recognized the right of unmarried persons to possess and distribute contraceptives on the same basis as married persons, and Roe,[130] which proclaimed that states could not prohibit all abortions except those undertaken to save a mother’s life, as such laws infringed on a woman’s right to privacy. Kennedy next turned to Bowers v. Hardwick,[131] which held that there is no fundamental right for gay people to engage in consensual sodomy. Kennedy insisted that, in Bowers, the 5–4 majority failed “to appreciate the extent of the liberty at stake. To say that the issue in Bowers was simply the right to engage in certain sexual conduct demeans the claim”[132] in that case. Indeed, the claims in both Bowers and Lawrence went far beyond the right to engage in sexual acts; they had “more far-reaching consequences, touching upon the most private human conduct, sexual behavior, and in the most private of places, the home,”[133] and thus should not be criminalized. Kennedy concluded by arguing that other recent privacy rulings had left the Bowers precedent in doubt, including Planned Parenthood of Southeastern Pennsylvania v. Casey[134] and Romer. In the process, he reversed Bowers.

Lawrence is a modernizing decision, Strauss has claimed, because “in deciding what ‘liberty’ meant, the Court used, among other things, a more or less explicit modernizing approach. In addition, the Court's definition of ‘liberty’ left many things undecided—significantly, for modernization purposes.”[135] Homosexual sodomy was not a traditional right, so the Lawrence Court “could assert only that ‘the historical grounds relied upon in Bowers are more complex’ than the Bowers Court had suggested.”[136] As Kennedy observed, “‘our laws and traditions in the past half century—rather than those of previous centuries—are of most relevance here.' Those more recent developments, according to the Court, ‘show an emerging awareness that liberty gives substantial protection to adult persons in deciding how to conduct their private lives in matters pertaining to sex.’”[137] Kennedy then surveyed a number of sources that indicated “’the emerging awareness,’” including that “of the twenty-five states that criminalized sodomy at the time of Bowers, only thirteen still had such prohibitions, and just four ‘enforce their laws only against homosexual conduct.’”[138] Thus, Strauss concluded, “the Lawrence Court's emphasis on an ‘emerging awareness’ is an explicit commitment to modernization.”[139]

XII.          Obergefell v. Hodges[140]

James Obergefell and John Arthur had been a same-sex Ohio couple for two decades, but as Arthur’s health deteriorated, the two men travelled to Maryland where—unlike Ohio—same-sex couples were legally allowed to marry. Following Arthur’s death, Ohio law also refused to allow Obergefell to be listed as the surviving spouse on Arthur’s death certificate. Obergefell challenged this Ohio law, lost in the lower courts, but the Supreme Court agreed to hear the case.

Justice Kennedy’s 5–4 Obergefell opinion ushered in a liberal new constitutional principle: that same-sex marriage is a fundamental constitutional right, and the Fourteenth Amendment’s Due Process and Equal Protection Clauses require states to issue marriage licenses to same-sex couples and recognize same-sex marriages authorized in other states.[141] In reaching these conclusions, Kennedy principally addressed the concept of liberty, as in Lawrence, which includes the right to express “intimate personal choices that define personal identity and beliefs.”[142] Within this notion of liberty is the right to enter into a same-sex marriage and to have it viewed as lawful because marriage is central to the “human condition.”[143] Additionally, the right to marry had long been established under the Equal Protection Clause, as in Loving v. Virginia,[144] and same-sex couples were denied equal protection if a state only recognized marriages by opposite-sex couples.

How should Obergefell be assessed in terms of American constitutional development? Strauss has noted that the Constitution’s text “made only a cameo appearance” in Obergefell.[145] The Court’s opinion mainly relied on principles from “the Court’s previous decisions; from ‘the Nation’s traditions’; and …. from the Court’s own essentially moral judgment that same-sex marriage should be permitted.”[146] The Due Process and Equal Protection Clauses were primarily relied on ceremonially, “as sources of inspiration, roughly in the way that a revered nonlegal document like the Declaration of Independence might.”[147] Obergefell was therefore anchored in abstract constitutional notions, “but in substance it is a common lawlike opinion; or at least a common law approach is broadly consistent with the Court’s own analysis and provides the most secure justification for the Court’s holding.”[148] Consequently, the majority relied on precedents declaring that the right to marry is fundamental and that laws are unfair that disapprove of gay and lesbian relationships. Further, lower courts had often upheld same-sex marriage claims, and those rulings served as precedent, as well.[149] Ultimately, the Obergefell Court chose a morally preferable approach, which “is characteristic of the common law.”[150] In the process, “precedents shape the text [of the Constitution], not the other way around,”[151] and common law constitutional interpretations best explain legal evolution—not originalist or textual interpretations.[152] Presumably, then, Obergefell was an evolutionary ruling.

XIII.       Bostock v. Clayton County[153]

According to Strauss, Bostock v. Clayton County was an evolutionary decision, like Obergefell but unlike Lawrence. Gerald Bostock, a child welfare worker in Clayton County, Georgia, was fired for conduct unbecoming a county employee due to his sexual orientation and association with a gay softball league.[154] Ruling in favor of Bostock, Justice Gorsuch delivered the 6–3 opinion for the Roberts Court, concluding that an employer who dismisses an employee for being gay or transgender violates Title VII of the Civil Rights Act of 1964.[155] Bostock was an unprecedented interpretation of Title VII, which prohibits employment discrimination “because of race, color, religion, sex, or national origin.”[156] Sexual orientation is not expressly mentioned in Title VII, but focusing on the prohibition of sex discrimination, Bostock dramatically broadened the meaning of sex to include sexual orientation. In Gorsuch’s words, Title VII requires that “an individual’s homosexuality or transgender status is not relevant to employment decisions. That’s because it is impossible to discriminate against a person for being homosexual or transgender without discriminating against that individual based on sex.”[157] Bostock’s impact may be wide-ranging, as federal and state civil rights laws typically prohibit sex discrimination. This may mean that, going forward, they are likely to be interpreted as prohibiting discrimination based on sexual orientation as well, which would make Bostock an evolutionary ruling, given Strauss’s theory.

So how does Strauss assess Bostock? The Roberts Court reached the correct conclusion in Bostock, Strauss argued, but its reasoning was seriously flawed in other ways. Most importantly, Gorsuch’s opinion was inconsistent with Congress’s intent in passing Title VII and the way Title VII had been interpreted by the courts since 1964.[158] Moreover, Gorsuch’s “narrow focus on the words of Title VII meant that [he] never considered the relationship between the issue in Bostock and the substantial body of constitutional law concerning sex discrimination, or the more recently developed constitutional protections for gay and lesbian people.”[159]

Strauss believed that these weaknesses in Gorsuch’s Bostock opinion are, by and large, explained by the Court’s focus on Title VII’s text alone (the phrase “because of … sex”) “as if the answer has been there ever since 1964, awaiting only the majority’s analysis of meaning and syntax to unlock it, and as if we have not learned anything in the intervening years.”[160] As we would anticipate, then, Strauss concluded that constitutional evolution—not textualism—provided the proper basis for deciding Bostock. For instance, Strauss emphasized that the evolution of case law denouncing “discrimination against gender nonconforming individuals was essentially complete” by the time Price Waterhouse v. Hopkins[161] was decided, so “why was it not apparent, long before Bostock, that sexual orientation discrimination was illegal?”[162] Finally, Strauss extended his argument by comparing constitutional evolution in Bostock to two legendary racial segregation cases: Plessy and Brown.

XIV.        Revising Evolution Theory

We return to the main question addressed in this article: How are transformational changes in American constitutional law best understood and conceptualized? In answering this question, we have emphasized the work of two distinguished legal theorists: first, Robert McCloskey, but then in far greater detail David Strauss. Though simple, McCloskey’s descriptive theory of three great constitutional eras in Supreme Court history was a breakthrough for its time. By contrast, Strauss has made an important contribution to the theory of constitutional development with his concepts of evolution and modernization. In myriad publications he has used these concepts to describe and compare Supreme Court decisions, especially those involving racial segregation and school desegregation, cruel and unusual punishment, sex and sexual orientation discrimination, freedom of speech and press, voting rights and reapportionment, and various aspects of privacy. Even so, Strauss’s concepts must be revised as scholars continue to investigate McCloskey’s original goal of determining when, how, and why fundamental constitutional change occurs over time.

First, Strauss’s major concepts are vague and should be clarified and refined. Precisely what is the scope of the meaning of constitutional evolution, and how does it differ from the notions of a “living Constitution” or an “unwritten Constitution”? If any of those concepts are synonymous, we should acknowledge that at the outset; if they are not interchangeable, we should explain the exact differences using prominent High Court rulings as illustrations. Modernization seems to be a more transparent concept. but at times there are also problems in how Strauss employs it.

Consider an example: Was Roe an evolutionary or a modernizing decision? In 2010, Strauss described Roe as an evolutionary ruling because “a plausible, precedent-based, common-law case can be made for a woman’s right to reproductive freedom” due to the “right to bodily integrity” and “the right to control the composition of one’s family.”[163] Yet the previous year Strauss maintained that Roe was a leading example of constitutional modernization. As he wrote then, although one can argue that Roe was evolutionary in nature, it “is still best seen as an exercise in modernization. Indeed, that may be one of the most satisfactory justifications for Roe.”[164] According to Strauss, “it is difficult to make a case that there was a traditional right to obtain an abortion. The right to control one's bodily integrity, reproductive capacity, and family composition do have some basis in tradition and the common law, and in constitutional precedents.” Yet “the problem comes in explaining why the state's interest in protecting fetal life did not override those rights; tradition (and, for that matter, moral reasoning) seems to be of little help on this point,” he argued. “But the core idea of modernization—that the trend in the nation as a whole was toward allowing the abortion decision to be made by individual women—would have provided some basis for the decision in Roe, and that trend undoubtedly influenced the Court.” In addition, “the more general trend toward a change in the status of women, which underlay the modernizing decisions about sex classifications, also must have played some role in the decision.”[165] Apparently, Roe has been a hard case for Strauss to classify theoretically as it can be interpreted as both an evolutionary and a modernization ruling.

This raises another question: Does Strauss simply reshuffle his deck by concluding that constitutional evolution occurred when the High Court modernized its decisions via judicial review? This question can best be answered by comparing Straus’s definitions for his modernizing and evolving constitutional concepts. Modernizing rulings have two things in common, according to Strauss. First, “modernization is, by nature, a centralizing approach, one that limits local or regional diversity in favor of a nationally uniform trend that, in the courts’ view, is ascendant.”[166] But based on Strauss’s own admission as presented above, various evolutionary decisions, including Brown, Reynolds, Gideon, Katz, Obergefell, and Bostock also had centralizing effects on the American federal system. Second, “the decisions that engaged in modernization are all ‘liberal’ in the sense in which that term is commonly used to describe Supreme Court decisions,” Strauss wrote. “More generally, the term ‘modernization’ might be taken to suggest progress, as if the decisions necessarily move the law to a more ‘modern,’ and therefore better, state of the world.”[167] But the concept of constitutional evolution—and even a “living constitution” or an “unwritten constitution”—can imply liberalism and constitutional progress. To use the same examples, Brown, Reynolds, Gideon, Katz, Obergefell, and Bostock certainly did. So how may we clearly distinguish constitutional modernization from constitutional evolution? Once more, greater conceptual clarity is necessary.

Second, new concepts should be advanced by Strauss and others to make evolution theory more comprehensive. Supreme Court cases that Strauss sometimes examines are “cherry picked”—chosen to support his conclusions. The overuse of Brown in his work is obvious.[168] New concepts would make his descriptive theory more robust but would not help to explain the causes of constitutional change. At a minimum, then, Strauss should consider formally adding at least three new descriptive concepts to his decisional analyses: retrogressive decisions, revolutionary decisions, and confirming status quo decisions.

Strauss has suggested that retrogression might be a part of descriptive constitutional evolution theory, although he has only mentioned it once, in passing. Consider the larger context of Strauss’s reference to retrogression. In commenting on the research of Ernst Young of Duke University, Strauss observed that constitutional “changes over time have not always been for the better. . . . As Professor Young says, any account of the Constitution and constitutional law has to acknowledge the possibility of retrogression, not just progress.”[169] Unfortunately, Strauss has yet to expand on the concept of retrogression—or of any related concept—in his published work. Here, therefore, is one concept that should receive further attention as it could relate to various decisions, including San Antonio School District v. Rodriguez,[170] Milliken v. Bradley,[171] New York State Rifle & Pistol Association v. Bruen,[172] and Dobbs.[173]

Likewise, perhaps a small number of Supreme Court rulings have theoretically been “revolutionary.” Strauss maintains that evolutionary adjustments in constitutional law are preferable to revolutionary alterations, but “revolutionary change remains possible, and tradition is not to be venerated beyond the point where the reasons for venerating it apply.”[174] So, in the end, which of the Warren Court holdings constituted revolutionary constitutional change, and why was revolutionary development not preferable to evolution? It is not clear how Strauss would reply, yet it still is a worthwhile question. What part of the Warren Court “revolution” would Strauss object to, preferring a more evolutionary approach instead? Not Brown, for he describes it as “the completion of an evolutionary, common-law process, not an isolated, pathbreaking act.”[175] Or take a different constitutional era and situation: if the doctrine of judicial review, as established in Marbury v. Madison,[176] represented a revolutionary constitutional development, what conceivable alternatives did Marshall, or his successors, have in order to establish the judiciary as a third coequal branch of government? If the power of judicial review is essential in this regard, why would Marbury not constitute revolutionary constitutional change? Perhaps it does, for Strauss says that judicial review is undemocratic, as the judiciary can overrule popular majority opinion. Nonetheless, he also has concluded that “most of us think that these ‘undemocratic’ features of our system [such as judicial review] are a good thing.”[177]

The idea of confirming status quo decisions is inherent in Strauss’s work, as well in McCloskey’s, but it is not singled out as a separate concept. Some cases like Cruzan obviously involve a category of rulings that are neither evolutionary, modernizing, retrogressive, nor revolutionary. A robust theory of constitutional development should contain concepts representing all basic aspects of real-world constitutional interpretation, including that the Supreme Court frequently upholds common law. In this sense, Strauss has not yet advanced a “theory,” as his amplification of two concepts—evolution and modernization—falls short of what is needed to analyze constitutional development and Supreme Court policymaking on a grander scale.

Even more important, Strauss should clarify whether he is presenting a theory of constitutional interpretation, a theory of constitutional causation, or both. Although his theory of interpretation is apparent, some of Strauss’s statements suggest causality, such as, “rules in constitutional law, like many other things in the world, are most often the product—the ongoing, unfinished product—of evolution.”[178] By contrast, McCloskey described both the Court’s evolutionary interpretation of the Constitution and proposed a causal theory by underscoring the enabling conditions that triggered basic constitutional changes from one great era to the next.

McCloskey’s attempt to develop a causal theory of constitutional change initially recognizes that “the interests and values, and hence the role, of the Court have shifted fundamentally and often in the presence of shifting national conditions.”[179] Given convulsive historical events or forces,[180] the Court has altered its focus, priorities, values, and policies in response to critical new political, legal, economic, and social circumstances. Following the Civil War, for example, the Court “adjusted itself and the Constitution to the altered conditions of the postwar order. Old problems like slavery had been forgotten,” McCloskey observed, as the Court’s principal focus turned to property rights and free enterprise. “The process of redefining the Court’s role, a process impelled by the transfiguration of the nation itself, was not complete to be sure,” he noted, “but the enabling conditions had been met.”[181]

Similarly, according to McCloskey, the Court adjusted its focus, priorities, values, and policies in the third great constitutional era away from property rights and toward minority rights. “History . . . had displaced the Court’s old ideal of free enterprise,”[182] and the Court “faced a future in which its interests of seventy years past were no longer relevant.”[183] But to remain relevant in the American legal and political system, the justices “needed to evolve a new sphere of interests and a new set of values to guide them within that sphere.”[184] Again, the Court had to “reorient [its] interests, to formulate another system of judicial values, and to develop a role for the Court,” especially because of the rise of totalitarianism in Germany and Russia, followed by the Cold War.[185] Obviously, McCloskey argued, considering these challenging international developments, the Court was forced to pay much greater attention to individual civil rights and liberties in America than it had in the past. McCloskey, ultimately, only suggested the early stages of a robust causal theory of constitutional change, but the idea that certain enabling conditions—be it the Civil War, the Great Depression, etc.—could force the Court to alter its focus, priorities, values, and policies went well beyond any theory of causation suggested by Strauss thus far. Whether Strauss has this goal in mind we know not, but if he does and accomplishes his objective, it will substantially enhance his contribution to the study of constitutional development and change in the United States.

 Evolutionary theory can additionally be strengthened by applying basic quantitative techniques to Supreme Court voting behavior over time. Charles Lamb and Jacob Neiheisel used an approach for identifying liberal and conservative evolutionary trends in the justice’s voting behavior on separation of powers, federalism, and economic rights cases.186 In doing so, they described how constitutional law has evolved on assorted issues.187

In the final analysis, Strauss, McCloskey, and other scholars are correct in concluding that constitutional evolution has been an innate feature of Supreme Court decision-making ever since Chief Justice Marshall underscored its existence in McCulloch.188 Constitutional evolution can be detected in a wide array of fields, including civil rights and liberties, using qualitative and even quantitative techniques. There are, however, considerable difficulties in how the concept has been used in the past. From a research perspective, Supreme Court students of all stripes should refine the and build upon the basic concept of constitutional evolutionary development as a permanent aspect of the Court’s role in American democracy, while also striving to develop a causal theory of how constitutional law evolves over time.

[1]86 Charles M. Lamb & Jacob R. Neiheisel, Constitutional Landmarks: Supreme Court Decisions on Separation of Powers, Federalism, and Economic Rights (2021).

[1]87 Id. at 10, 12, 22, 184, 185, 224, 225, 227, 236.

[1]88 Supra note 10.

 



[1] See, e.g., David Leonhardt, The Impatient, Ambitious Five, N.Y. Times (June 27, 2022).

[2] 410 U.S. 113 (1973).

[3] 597 U.S. ___ (2022).

[4] Robert G. McCloskey, The American Supreme Court (1960). McCloskey’s book is currently in its sixth edition, and his theoretical framework is concisely stated at id. 15.

[5] See id. at chaps. 3–4.

[6] See id. at chaps. 5–6.

[7] See id. at chap. 7. Since McCloskey’s original work in chapter 7, the Court’s major decisions during the civil rights era have been explored in chapters 8 and 9 by Sanford Levinson of the University of Texas Law School. For an evaluation of McCloskey’s theory, see Stephen C. Halpern & Charles M. Lamb, The Supreme Court and New Constitutional Eras, 64 Brook. L. Rev. 1183 (1998).

[8] See, e.g., Antonin Scalia, Originalism: The Lesser Evil, 57 U. Cin. L. Rev. 849 (1989); David A. Strauss, The Living Constitution (2010).

[9] See, e.g., Bruce Ackerman, The Living Constitution, 120 Harv. L. Rev. 1737 (2007); William J. Brennan, Construing the Constitution, U.C. Davis L. Rev. 19 (1985); William H. Rehnquist, The Notion of a Living Constitution, 54 Tex. L. Rev. 693 (1976). As used by some scholars, the notion of an “unwritten Constitution” is very similar to, if not synonymous with, a “living Constitution.” See, e.g., Akhil Reed Amar, America’s Unwritten Constitution: The Precedents and Principles We Live By (2012).

[10] 4 Wheaton 316 (1819).

[11] Id. at 407, 415 (emphasis in original).

[12] See, e.g., Geoffrey R. Stone, Precedent, the Amendment Process, and Evolution in Constitutional Doctrine, 11 Harv. J. of L. & Pub. Pol. 67 (1987); David A. Strauss, Common Law Constitutional Interpretation, 63 U. Chi. L. Rev. 877 (1996); David A. Strauss, The Irrelevance of Constitutional Amendments, 114 Harv. L. Rev. 1457 (2001).

[13] See, e.g., Strauss, Common Law Constitutional Interpretation, id.; Strauss, The Irrelevance of Constitutional Amendments, id. Strauss has cited McCloskey’s publications on occasion but not with respect to his theory of three great constitutional eras.

[14] Geoffrey R. Stone & David A. Strauss, Democracy and Equality: The Enduring Constitutional Vision of the Warren Court (2020).

[15] Political scientists also occasionally rely on some form of evolution theory in their work. See Edward G. Carmines & James A. Stimson, Issue Evolution: Race and the Transformation of American Politics (1989); Eric Schickler, Racial Realignment: The Transformation of American Liberalism, 1932–1965 (2016).

[16] Strauss, Common Law Constitutional Interpretation, supra note 12; Strauss, The Irrelevance of Constitutional Amendments, supra note 12.

[17] 347 U.S. 483 (1954).

[18] 367 U.S. 643 (1961).

[19] 381 U.S. 479 (1965).

[20] 384 U.S. 436 (1966).

[21] David A. Strauss, New Textualism in Constitutional Law, 66 Geo. Wash. L. Rev. 1153, 1158 (1997).

[22] Strauss, Common Law Constitutional Interpretation, supra note 12, at 884.

[23] David A. Strauss, Does the Constitution Mean What It Says?, 129 Harv. L. Rev. 1, 47 (2015).

[24] David A. Strauss, The Modernizing Mission of Judicial Review, 76 U. Chi. L. Rev. 859 (2009).

[25] Id. at 860. Strauss has claimed that Brown was “the most celebrated modernizing decision of all.” Id. at 904. However, more often, he has insisted that Brown was an evolutionary ruling. See, e.g., Strauss, supra note 8, at 85, where he concludes that “Brown was the completion of an evolutionary, common law process, not an isolated, pathbreaking act.”

[26] Id. at 860.

[27] 217 U.S. 349 (1910).

[28] Strauss, supra note 25, at 864.

[29] Id.

[30] 347 U.S. 497 (1954).

[31] Supra note 18.

[32] 339 U.S. 629 (1950).

[33] 339 U.S. 637 (1950).

[34] David A. Strauss, Not Unwritten, After All? 126 Harv. L. Rev. 1541 (2013).

[35] Id. at 1543.

[36] Strauss, supra note 24, at 44.

[37] Strauss, supra note 35, at 1541. See also Strauss, supra note 24, at 43–45.

[39] Id.

[40] Id. at 499–500.

[41] 163 U.S. 537 (1896).

[42] 372 U.S. 335 (1963).

[43] Id. at 336–38.

[44] 316 U.S. 445 (1942).

[45] Id. at 457.

[46] Id. at 462.

[47] 287 U.S. 45 (1932)

[48] 316 U.S., supra note 45, at 471–72.

[49] 304 U.S. 458 (1938).

[50] 316 U.S., supra note 45, at 471.

[51] 372 U.S., supra note 43, at 345.

[52] Stone & Strauss, supra note 14, at 53.

[53] Id. at 58.

[54] Id. at 60.

[55] 377 U.S. 533 (1964).

[56] 369 U.S. 186 (1962).

[57] 377 U.S., supra note 56, at 561–62.

[58] Id. at 565.

[59] Id. at 572–75.

[60] Id. at 577.

[61] Stone & Strauss, supra note 14, at 86–87. Colegrove v. Green, 328 U.S. 549 (1946), ruled that federal courts lacked the power to interfere with the malapportionment of congressional districts.

[62] Stone & Strauss, supra note 14, at 87.

[63] Id.

[64] Id.

[65] Id.

[66] Id. at 88.

[67] 389 U.S. 347 (1967).

[68] 277 U.S. 438 (1928).

[69] Id. at 455, 459.

[70] Id. at 464.

[71] Id.

[72] 389 U.S., supra note 68, at 348.

[73] Id. at 351.

[74] 316 U.S. 129 (1942).

[75] 389 U.S., supra note 68, at 356.

[76] Stone & Strauss, supra note 14, at 128–29.

[77] Id.

[78] Id. at 129.

[79] Id.

[80] Id.

[81] Strauss, supra note 8.

[82] 401 U.S. 745 (1971).

[83] 476 U.S. 207 (1988).

[84] 533 U.S. 27 (2001).

[85] 565 U.S. 400 (2012).

[86] 403 U.S. 713 (1971).

[87] Id. at 714.

[88] Sheldon Goldman, Constitutional Law: Cases and Essays (1991), 475.

[89] 403 U.S., supra note 87, at 713.

[90] Id. at 718–19.

[91] Id. at 723–24.

[92] Id. at 724.

[93] Id. at 725.

[94] Id.

[95] Strauss, supra note 8, at 75.

[96] Id.

[97] Id. at 76.

[98] Id.

[99] Id.

[100] 497 U.S. 261 (1990).

[101] Id. at 266–67.

[102] Id. at 266–68.

[103] Id. at 268–69.

[104] Id. at 281–82.

[105] Id. at 284–85.

[106] Id.

[107] Id. at 284.

[108] 518 U.S. 515 (1996).

[109] Id. at 520–30.

[110] Id. at 556–57.

[111] Id. at 548.

[112] 458 U.S. 718 (1982).

[113] 518 U.S. supra note 109, at 534–40.

[114] Id. at 538–39.

[115] Strauss, supra note 25, at 872.

[116] Id., at 873.

[117] Id.

[118] 539 U.S. 558 (2003).

[119] Id. at 562–63.

[120] Id. at 563.

[121] 517 U.S. 620 (1996).

[122] 570 U.S. 744 (2013).

[123] 576 U.S. 644 (2015).

[124] 539 U.S., supra note 119, at 558.

[125] Id. at 564.

[126] 381 U.S., supra note 20, at 479.

[127] 539 U.S., supra note 119, at 564–65.

[128] 381 U.S., supra note 20, at 483.

[129] 405 U.S. 438 (1972).

[130] 410 U.S., supra note 2, at 113.

[131] 478 U.S. 186 (1986).

[132] 539 U.S., supra note 119, at 567.

[133] Id.

[134] 505 U.S. 833 (1992).

[135] Strauss, supra note 25, at 885.

[136] Id.

[137] Kennedy quoted at id.

[138] Id. at 886.

[139] Id.

[140] 576 U.S., supra note 124, at 644. Page citations to Obergefell are to the Court’s slip opinion.

[141] Id., Obergefell slip opinion, at 12–14.

[142] Id. at 10.

[143] Id. at 3.

[144] 388 U.S. 1 (1967).

[145] Strauss, supra note 24, at 6.

[146] Id.

[147] Id.

[148] Id. at 6–7.

[149] Id.

[150] Id. at 7.

[151] Id. at 6–7.

[152] Id. at 17. For an elaboration of this argument, see Strauss, Common Law Constitutional Interpretation, supra note 12; Strauss, supra note 8.

[153] 140 S. Ct. 1731 (2020). Page citations to Bostock are to the Court’s slip opinion.

[154] Id., Bostock slip opinion, at 2–3.

[155] 42 U.S.C. § 2000e-2(a)(1).

[156] Bostock slip opinion, supra note 132, at 9.

[157] David A. Strauss, Sexual Orientation and the Dynamics of Discrimination, Sup. Ct. Rev. 203 (2021).

[158] Id. at 203–204.

[159] Id. at 204.

[160] Id. at 221.

[161] 490 U.S. 228 (1989). Price Waterhouse ruled that gender stereotyping is actionable as sex discrimination under Title VII.

[162] Strauss, supra note 158, at 222–23.

[163] Strauss, supra note 8, at 94–95.

[164] Strauss, supra note 25, at 901.

[165] Id. at 887.

[166] Id.

[167] Id.

[168] See, e.g., Strauss, supra note 8, at 77–92; Stone & Strauss, supra note 14, at 13–26; Strauss, supra note 35, at 1540–45; David A. Strauss, The Common Law Genius of the Warren Court, 49 Wm. & Mary L. Rev. 845 (2007).

[169] David A. Strauss, The Living Constitution and Moral Progress: A Comment on Professor Young’s Boden Lecture, 102 Marq. L. Rev. 980 (2019).

[170] 411 U.S. 1 (1973).

[171] 418 U.S. 717 (1974).

[172] 597 U.S. ___ (2022).

[173] Supra note 3.

[174] Strauss, Common Law Constitutional Interpretation, supra note 12, at 895.

[175] Strauss, supra note 8, at 85.

[176] 1 Cranch 137 (1803).

[177] Strauss, supra note 8, at 47.

[178] David A. Strauss, On the Origin of Rules (with Apologies to Darwin), 75 U. Chi. L. Rev. 1013 (2008) (emphasis added).

[179] McCloskey, supra note 4 at 208.

[180] Halpern and Lamb, supra note 7 at 1189, define a convulsive historical event or force (CHEF) as a “dramatic, precipitous occurrence that disrupts the political foundations of the nation so deeply that the political system undergoes fundamental and enduring transformations.” Yet a CHEF “does not cause a new constitutional period. It is a necessary, but not a sufficient, condition for producing that new era.” Id. at 1190. 

[181] McCloskey, supra note 4 at 89–90.

[182] Id. at 122.

[183] Id. at 119.

[184] Id. at 121.

[185] Id. at 122.








CURRICULUM VITAE

CHARLES M. LAMB

Department of Political Science

University at Buffalo

The State University of New York

520 Park Hall, North Campus

Buffalo, New York 14260

e-mail: clamb@buffalo.edu

Webpage: http://www.polsci.buffalo.edu/faculty_staff/lamb/

Education        

Ph.D., University of Alabama, 1974 (Political Science)

M.A., University of Alabama, 1970 (Political Science)

B.S., Middle Tennessee State University, 1967 (Political Science) (highest honors)

Career

Research Professor of Political Science, University at Buffalo, The State University of New York, 2018-present

Professor Emeritus of Political Science, University at Buffalo, The State University of New York, 2018-present

Professor of Political Science, University at Buffalo, The State University of New York, 2006-2018

 

Associate Professor of Political Science, University at Buffalo, The State University of New York, 1984-2006

Distinguished Visiting Associate Professor, Robert M. La Follette Institute of Public Affairs, University of Wisconsin-Madison, 1990-1991

Assistant Professor of Political Science, The State University of New York at Buffalo, 1977-1984

 

Equal Opportunity Specialist and Fair Housing Monitor, Office of Federal Civil Rights

Enforcement, U.S. Commission on Civil Rights, Washington, DC, 1975-1977

Consultant, Office of Technology Assessment, U.S. Congress, Washington, DC, 1975-1976

Research Scientist, Program of Policy Studies in Science and Technology, The George Washington University, Washington, DC, 1973-1975

Graduate Teaching Assistant, Department of Political Science, University of Alabama, 1970-1973

 

Administrative Specialist, Office of Policy Analysis, National Aeronautics and Space Administration, Washington, DC, summer, 1971

National Defense Education Act Fellow, Department of Political Science, University of Alabama, 1967-1970

Cataloguer, Justice Harold H. Burton's Supreme Court Papers, Manuscript Division, Library of Congress, Washington, DC, summer, 1966

Academic Interests

Currently I have two primary interests. One is a series of articles, culminating in a book, on the use of presidential and bureaucratic power in fair housing policy, 1960-present. Second is a book on constitutional change in Supreme Court civil rights and civil liberties decision-making, 1900-present. Fields: Public Law (constitutional law, civil liberties, and judicial politics); Public Policy (civil rights policy making, implementation, and enforcement); American Politics (presidency, bureaucracy, courts, Congress, federalism, urban and ethnic politics); Politics and History (especially since 1900).

 

Books

The Supreme Court, Constitutional Change, and Individual Rights (co-author with Jacob R. Neiheisel) (in preparation).

Presidents, Bureaucracy, and Fair Housing in America (co-author with Jacob R. Neiheisel) (in preparation).

Constitutional Landmarks: Supreme Court Decisions on Separation of Powers, Federalism, and Economic Rights (co-author with Jacob R. Neiheisel) (New York: Palgrave Macmillan, 2021), pp. xiii + 288.

Presidential Leadership and the Trump Presidency: Executive Power and Democratic

Government (co-editor and co-author with Jacob R. Neiheisel) (New York: Palgrave Macmillan, 2020), pp. vii + 185. (The Evolving Presidency Series.)

 

Housing Segregation in Suburban America since 1960: Presidential and Judicial Politics (author) (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2005), pp. xii + 302.

The Burger Court: Political and Judicial Profiles (co-editor and co-author with Stephen C. Halpern) (Urbana: University of Illinois Press, 1991), pp. x + 513. (Edited book of original essays.)

Judicial Conflict and Consensus: Behavioral Studies of American Appellate Courts (co-editor and co-author with Sheldon Goldman) (Lexington: University Press of Kentucky, 1986), pp. xi + 305. (Edited book of original essays.)

Implementation of Civil Rights Policy (co-editor and co-author with Charles S. Bullock III) (Monterey, CA: Brooks/Cole Publishing Co., Wadsworth, Inc., 1984), pp. xiii + 223. (Edited book of original essays.) (Brooks/Cole Public Policy Series.)

Supreme Court Activism and Restraint (co-editor and co-author with Stephen C. Halpern) (Lexington, MA: Lexington Books, D.C. Heath & Co., 1982), pp. xi + 436. (Edited book of original essays.) Choice Outstanding Academic Book Award, 1983.

Articles, Chapters, Short Monographs

"Federalism, Civil Rights, and Housing: The Evolving Role of State and Local Governments," (with Charles S. Bullock III and Eric M. Wilk) (under review).

“Administrative Discretion and the Politics of Workload Filtration,” (with Charles S. Bullock III and Eric M. Wilk) (under review).

 

“The Supreme Court, Constitutional Development, and Evolution Theory: A Critique,” (with Jacob R. Neiheisel) (under review).

 

“Race, Ethnicity, and Fair Housing Enforcement: A Regional Analysis” (with Charles S. Bullock III and Eric M. Wilk) BYU Journal of Public Law (forthcoming 2023).

 

“African American and Latino Discrimination Complaints: Comparing Volume and Outcomes,” Social Science Quarterly 102(6): 2676-2688 (2021) (with Charles S. Bullock III and Eric M. Wilk).

"Memo to President Biden on State and Local Fair Housing Enforcement," New York University Journal of Legislation and Public Policy Quorum (2021) (with Charles S. Bullock III and Eric M. Wilk).

“On Studying the Trump Presidency,” Presidential Leadership and the Trump Presidency: Executive Power and Democratic Government (New York: Palgrave Macmillian, 2020), ch. 1, pp. 1-19 (with Jacob R. Neiheisel). Charles M. Lamb and Jacob R. Neiheisel, eds.

“Presidential Rhetoric and Bureaucratic Enforcement: The Clinton Administration and Civil Rights,” Political Science Quarterly 134(2): 277-302 (2019) (with Joshua Boston and Jacob R. Neiheisel).

“Power Plus Persuasion: The Anatomy of Kennedy’s Housing Order,” Congress and the Presidency 46(2): 109-134 (2019) (with Joshua Boston and Jacob R. Neiheisel).

“Cooperative Federalism and Fair Housing Enforcement,” Social Science Quarterly 99(2): 728-743 (2018) (with Charles S. Bullock III and Eric M. Wilk).

 

"Bureaucratic Effectiveness and Civil Rights Enforcement,” State and Local Government Review 49(2): 87-104 (2017) (with Charles S. Bullock III and Eric M. Wilk). See also “State and Local Agencies Are More Effective Than the Federal Government in Housing Discrimination Enforcement,” London School of Economics’ American Politics and Policy Blog, November 15, 2017 (with Bullock and Wilk).

 

“HMDA, Housing Segregation, and Racial Disparities in Mortgage Lending,” Stanford Journal of Civil Rights and Civil Liberties 12(2): 249-282 (2016) (with Randolph S. Kent, Jacqueline M. Sievert, Michael R. Staszkiw, and Elizabeth A. Tillman).

 

“Fair Housing Enforcement in the South and Non-South,” Social Science Quarterly 96(4):

941-954 (2015) (with Charles S. Bullock III and Eric M. Wilk).

"School and Housing Segregation," The Oxford Handbook on Racial and Ethnic Politics in the United States (New York: Oxford Handbooks Online, 2014) (with Charles S. Bullock III). David L. Leal, Taeku Lee, and Mark Sawyer, eds.

“Administrative Law Judges in Fair Housing Enforcement: Attitudes, Case Facts, and Political Control, Social Science Quarterly 94(2): 362-378 (2013) (with Nicholas R. Seabrook and Eric M. Wilk).

 

“Do Presidents Control Bureaucracy? The Federal Housing Administration during the Truman-Eisenhower Era,” Political Science Quarterly 127(3): 445-467 (2012) (with Adam W. Nye).

“Federalism, Efficiency, and Civil Rights Enforcement,” Political Research Quarterly 64(3): 392-404 (2011) (with Eric M. Wilk).

“Intergovernmental Enforcement of the Fair Housing Act: The Fair Housing Assistance

Program,” Fair and Affordable Housing Policy in the United States: Trends, Outcomes, Future Directions (Leiden, The Netherlands: Brill Academic Publishers, 2011) (Studies in Critical

Social Sciences Series), ch. 2, pp. 21-40 (with Eric M. Wilk and Nicholas R. Seabrook). Robert Mark Silverman and Kelly L. Patterson, eds. (Paperback edition, 2012, Haymarket Books, Chicago, IL).

“The Federal Courts and Fair Housing Policy: A Principal-Agent Interpretation,” Fair and

Affordable Housing Policy in the United States: Trends, Outcomes, Future Directions (Leiden, The Netherlands: Brill Academic Publishers, 2011) (Studies in Critical Social Sciences Series), ch. 3, pp. 41-65 (with Eric M. Wilk and Nicholas R. Seabrook). Robert Mark Silverman and Kelly L. Patterson, eds. (Paperback edition, 2012, Haymarket Books, Chicago, IL).

“Civil Rights, Federalism, and the Administrative Process: Favorable Outcomes by Federal, State, and Local Agencies in Housing Discrimination Complaints,” Public Administration Review 70(3): 412-421 (2010) (with Eric M. Wilk).  

“Presidents, Bureaucracy, and Housing Discrimination Policy: The Fair Housing Acts of 1968 and 1988,” Politics and Policy 37(1): 127-149 (2009) (with Eric M. Wilk).  

“Presidential Influence and Centralization: The Case of Nixon and George Romney," Politics and Policy 29(1): 91-119 (2001) (with Jim Twombly).

"Warren E. Burger," in The Scribner Encyclopedia of American Lives (New York: Charles Scribner's Sons, 2001), Vol. 4, pp. 61-64.

"The Supreme Court and New Constitutional Eras," Brooklyn Law Review 64: 1183-1203 (1998) (with Stephen C. Halpern).

United States v. Nixon Revisited: A Case Study in Supreme Court Decision-Making," University of Pittsburgh Law Review 58: 71-108 (1996) (with Lisa K. Parshall).

"Decentralizing Fair Housing Enforcement during the Reagan Presidency," Presidential Leadership and Civil Rights Policy (Westport, CT: Greenwood Press, 1995), ch. 9, pp. 127-148 (with Jim Twombly). Donald W. Jackson and James W. Riddlesperger, eds.

"Taking the Local: The Reagan Administration, New Federalism, and Fair Housing Implementation," Policy Studies Journal 21: 589-598 (1993) (with Jim Twombly).

“Fair Housing Implementation from Nixon to Reagan,” (Madison: Robert M. LaFollette Institute of Public Affairs, University of Wisconsin-Madison, 1992), Working Paper #11 pp. 24 (short monograph).

"The Political and Historical Context of the Burger Court," The Burger Court: Political and Judicial Profiles (Urbana: University of Illinois Press, 1991), ch. 1, pp. 1-34 (with Stephen C. Halpern). Charles M. Lamb and Stephen C. Halpern, eds.

"Chief Justice Warren E. Burger: A Conservative Chief for Conservative Times," The Burger Court: Political and Judicial Profiles (Urbana: University of Illinois Press, 1991), ch. 5, pp. 129-162. Charles M. Lamb and Stephen C. Halpern, eds.

"The Burger Court and Beyond," The Burger Court: Political and Judicial Profiles (Urbana: University of Illinois Press, 1991), ch. 15, pp. 433-461 (with Stephen C. Halpern). Charles M. Lamb and Stephen C. Halpern, eds.

The Supreme Court, Intent to Discriminate, and Fair Housing: An Exploration (Buffalo, NY: Baldy Center for Law and Social Policy, SUNY at Buffalo, 1988), pp. 63 (short monograph) (with George M. Borkowski).

"Racial Discrimination and Equal Opportunity," Encyclopedia of the American Judicial System: Studies of the Principal Institutions and Processes of Law (New York: Charles Scribner's Sons, Macmillan, 1987), III: 1195-1211. Robert J. Janosik, ed.

"Prologue," Judicial Conflict and Consensus: Behavioral Studies of American Appellate Courts (Lexington: University Press of Kentucky, 1986), pp. 1-18 (with Sheldon Goldman). Sheldon Goldman and Charles M. Lamb, eds.

"A Microlevel Analysis of Appeals Court Conflict: Warren Burger and His Colleagues on the D.C. Circuit," Judicial Conflict and Consensus: Behavioral Studies of American Appellate Courts (Lexington: University Press of Kentucky, 1986), ch. 8, pp. 179-196. Sheldon Goldman and Charles M. Lamb, eds.

 

"Epilogue," Judicial Conflict and Consensus: Behavioral Studies of American Appellate Courts (Lexington: University Press of Kentucky, 1986), ch. 1, pp. 275-291 (with Sheldon Goldman). Sheldon Goldman and Charles M. Lamb, eds.

"Education and Housing," The Reagan Administration and Human Rights (New York: Praeger, 1985), ch.4, pp. 82-105. Tinsley E. Yarbrough, ed.

"When Judicial Agreement Seems Impossible: Warren Burger, David Bazelon, and the D.C. Court of Appeals," Journal of Political Science 11: 75-82 (1984).

 

"A Search for Variables Important in Policy Implementation," Implementation of Civil Rights Policy (Monterey, CA: Brooks/Cole Publishing Co., Wadsworth, Inc., 1984), ch. 1, pp. 1-19 (with Charles S. Bullock III). Charles S. Bullock III and Charles M. Lamb, eds.

"Equal Housing Opportunity," Implementation of Civil Rights Policy (Monterey, CA:

Brooks/Cole Publishing Co., Wadsworth, Inc., 1984), ch. 6, pp. 148-183. Charles S. Bullock III and Charles M. Lamb, eds.

"Congressional-Constituent Communications," Southeastern Political Review [now Politics and Policy] 11: 93-110 (1983) (with Fred B. Wood).

“Judicial Restraint on the Supreme Court,” Supreme Court Activism and Restraint (Lexington, MA.: Lexington Books, D.C. Heath & Co., 1982), ch. 1, pp. 7-36. Stephen C. Halpern and Charles M. Lamb, eds.

"Toward a Theory of Civil Rights Implementation," Policy Perspectives 2: 376-393 (1982) (with Charles S. Bullock III).

"Congress, the Courts, and Civil Rights: The Fair Housing Act of 1968 Revisited," Villanova Law Review 27: 1115-1162 (1982).

"Judicial Restraint Reappraised," Catholic University Law Review 31: 181-199 (1982).

"Legal Foundations of Civil Rights and Pluralism in America," Annals of the American Academy of Political and Social Science 454: 13-25 (1981).

"Housing Discrimination and Segregation in America: Problematical Dimensions and the Federal Legal Response," Catholic University Law Review 30: 363-430 (1981).

"Presidential Leadership, Governmental Reorganization, and Equal Employment Opportunity," Employment and Labor-Relations Policy (Lexington, MA: Lexington Books, D.C. Heath and Co., 1980), ch. 6, pp. 81-98. Charles Bulmer and John C. Carmichael, eds.

"Equal Employment Opportunity and the Carter Administration: An Analysis of Reform Options," Policy Studies Journal 8: 377-383 (1979).

"The Burger Court, Exclusionary Zoning, and the Activist-Restraint Debate," University of Pittsburgh Law Review 40: 169-226 (1979) (with Mitchell S. Lustig).

"Counsel for the United States," Boston University Law Review 59: 196-208 (1979) (review essay).

"The Courts and Social Policy," U.C.L.A. Law Review 26: 234-252 (1978) (review essay).

"Administrative Coordination in Civil Rights Enforcement: A Regional Approach," Vanderbilt Law Review 31: 855-886 (1978).

"'New Federalism' and Civil Rights," University of Toledo Law Review 9: 816-845 (1978).

"Government by Judiciary," Emory Law Journal 27: 705-715 (1978) (review essay).

"Presidential Fair Housing Policies: Political and Legal Trends," Cumberland Law Review 8: 619-660 (1978).

"A Legislative Proposal for Improving Materials Policy-Making: Impacts and Issues," Washington University Law Quarterly 535-569 (1977) (with Fred B. Wood, Karen L. Larson, and Vary T. Coates).

U.S. Commission on Civil Rights, The Federal Civil Rights Enforcement Effort: To Preserve, Protect, and Defend the Constitution (Washington, DC: U.S. Government Printing Office, 1977), ch. 1 ("The White House"), pp. 1-77 (with Cynthia N. Graae), and ch. 3 ("The Federal Regional Councils"), pp. 124-159 (author).

"Exploring the Conservatism of Federal Appeals Court Judges," Indiana Law Journal 51: 257-279 (1976).

"Improving Public Policy-Making in an Age of Materials Scarcity," Iowa Law Review 62: 381-423 (1976) (with Fred B. Wood and Karen L. Larson).

"Judicial Policy-Making and Information Flow to the Supreme Court," Vanderbilt Law Review 29: 45-124 (1976).

U.S. Congress, Office of Technology Assessment, An Assessment of Information Systems

Capabilities Required to Support U.S. Materials Policy Decisions (Washington, DC: U.S.

Government Printing Office, 1976), chs. 5-8 ("Options for Achieving Integrated Capabilities," "Alternative Institutional Arrangements for Implementation," "Analysis of Possible Impacts," and "Identification and Analysis of Policy Issues"), pp. 115-225 (with Fred B. Wood).

Land Use Politics and Law in the 1970s (Washington, DC: The George Washington University Program of Policy Studies in Science and Technology, Monograph 28, 1975), pp. 90 (short monograph).

"The Making of a Chief Justice: Warren Burger on Criminal Procedure, 1956-1969," Cornell Law Review 60: 743-788 (1975).

Trends in State and Federal Land Use Law Relating to Inventories, Monitoring and Evaluation (Springfield, VA: National Technical Information Service, 1974), pp. 82 (short monograph).

"Warren Burger and the Insanity Defense: Judicial Philosophy and Voting Behavior on a U.S. Court of Appeals," American University Law Review 24: 91-128 (1974).

 

Working Papers

“Regional Civil Rights Enforcement for African Americans and Latinos” (with Charles S. Bullock III and Eric M. Wilk).

"Variations in Regional Civil Rights Enforcement.”

“Presidents, the Justice Department, and Civil Rights: The Politics of Housing Segregation and Discrimination.”

"State Fair Housing Laws and Current Levels of Segregation.”

“Fair Housing in the American States.” 

“Frontiers in Discrimination Policy: Disabilities and Families with Children.”  

“Fair Housing in U.S. Metropolitan Areas.” 

Book Reviews

J. Eric Oliver, The Paradoxes of Integration: Race, Neighborhood, and Civic Life in Multiethnic America (Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press, 2010) in the Journal of Politics 73: 1288-1290 (2011).

Leonard S. Rubinowitz and James E. Rosenbaum, Crossing the Class and Color Lines: From Public Housing to White Suburbia (Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press, 2000) in The Law and Politics Book Review 11: 91-93 (2001).

Charles M. Haar, Suburbs under Siege: Race, Space, and Audacious Judges (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1996) in The Law and Politics Book Review 6: 138-140 (1996).

Malcolm L. Goggin, Ann O'M. Bowman, James P. Lester, and Laurence J. O'Toole, Jr.,

Implementation Theory and Practice: Toward a Third Generation (Glenview, IL: Scott, Foresman/ Little, Brown, 1990), in the American Political Science Review 85: 267-268 (1991).

 

Herman Schwartz, ed., The Burger Years: Rights and Wrongs in the Supreme Court 1969-1986 (New York: Viking Press, 1987), in the American Political Science Review 82: 304-305 (1988).

Robert A. Carp and C.K. Rowland, Policymaking and Politics in the Federal District Courts (Knoxville: University of Tennessee Press, 1983), in the American Political Science Review 78: 215-216 (1984).

Daniel A. Mazmanian and Paul A. Sabitier, Implementation and Public Policy (Chicago, IL: Scott, Foresman, 1983), in Policy Sciences 17: 95-97 (1984).

Herbert Jacob, Crime and Justice in Urban America (Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall, 1980) in the American Political Science Review 75: 773-774 (1981).

Robert Livingston, Fair Game? Inequality and Affirmative Action (San Francisco, CA: W.H. Freeman and Co., 1979), in the Journal of Politics 43: 240-241 (1981).

Bob Woodward and Scott Armstrong, The Brethren: Inside the Supreme Court (New York: Simon and Schuster, 1979), in the Western Political Quarterly 33: 423-424 (1980).

Allan P. Sindler, Bakke, DeFunis, and Minority Admissions: The Quest for Equal Opportunity (New York: Longman Publishing Co., 1978), in the American Political Science Review 73: 1161-1162 (1979).

Ellis Sandoz, Conceived in Liberty: American Individual Rights Today (North Scituate, MA: Duxbury Press, 1978), in the Western Political Quarterly 32: 350-351 (1979)

Sheldon Goldman and Austin Sarat, eds., American Court Systems: Readings in Judicial Process and Behavior (San Francisco, CA: W.H. Freeman and Co., 1978), in the Journal of Politics 41: 737 (1979) (briefer notice).

James Eisenstein, Counsel for the United States: U.S. Attorneys in the Political and Legal Systems (Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1978), in the Journal of Politics 41: 281-283 (1979).

Richard Funston, A Vital National Seminar: The Supreme Court in American Political Life (Palo

Alto, CA: Mayfield Publishing Co., 1978); and Richard Funston, Constitutional Counterrevolution? The Warren Court and the Burger Court: Judicial Policy Making in Modern America (New York: Schenkman Publishing Co., 1977), in the Western Political Quarterly 32: 237-238 (1979).

 

Suzanne Weaver, Decision to Prosecute: Organization and Public Policy in the Antitrust Division (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1977), in the Journal of Politics 40: 1128-1129 (1978) (briefer notice).

Raoul Berger, Government by Judiciary: The Transformation of the Fourteenth Amendment (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1977), in the Western Political Quarterly 31: 438-439 (1978).

 

Professional Service

American Political Science Association:

Member, Best Paper Presented at the 2018 APSA Conference, Presidents and Executive Politics

Section, 2018-2019  

Member, Lifetime Achievement Award Committee, Law and Courts Section, 2014-2015

Member, Executive Committee, Law and Courts Section, 1984-1986, 1992-1994   Associate Editor, Law & Courts Newsletter, Law and Courts Section, 1985-1990

New York State Political Science Association:

President, 1985-1986

Vice President and Program Chair for 24 panels, 1984-1985

Member, Executive Council, 1982-1987

Section Chair for Public Law and Judicial Politics Panels, 1982-1984 Awards Committee, 1991

Northeastern Political Science Association:

Member, Executive Council, American Politics, 1983-1984

Occasional manuscript referee:

American Journal of Political Science

American Political Science Review

Armed Forces and Society

Congress and the Presidency

Journal of Politics

Judicature

Justice System Journal

Law and Policy

Law and Policy Quarterly

Policy Studies Review

Polity

Public Administration Review

Social Science Quarterly

Western Political Quarterly

Occasional reviewer of funding proposals:

National Science Foundation, Political Science Program

National Science Foundation, Law and Social Sciences Program

American Philosophical Society

National Endowment for the Humanities

Occasional reviewer of book manuscripts and book proposals:

D.C. Heath

Harper & Row

McGraw-Hill

Oxford University Press

 

See also Related Professional Activity Below

 

Conference Participation

American Political Science Association: 1977, 1979-1986, 1990-1992, 1995, 1999, 2002, 2005-2006, 2009-2014, 2017-2018

Midwest Political Science Association: 1979, 1984, 1988, 1995, 1997, 1999, 2002, 2006-2018

Southern Political Science Association: 1976, 1982, 1987, 2010, 2012-2015, 2017

Northeastern Political Science Association: 1980, 1983, 2008-2010

New York State Political Science Association: 1982-1983, 1986, 1989, 1992, 2005, 2011

New England Political Science Association: 2008

Conference Presentations (selected since 2010)

“African Americans, Latinos, and Fair Housing Enforcement in the U.S.,” Lightening Talk Panel on Public Policymaking, Midwest Political Science Association Conference, Chicago, IL, April 6, 2018 (with Charles S. Bullock III and Eric M. Wilk).

“Presidential Preferences and Bureaucratic Performance: Fair Housing Enforcement at DOJ,” Panel on Constraints on Unilateral Action, American Political Science Association Conference, San Francisco, CA, September 2, 2017 (with Collin J. Anderson, Daniel C. Myers, and Eric M. Wilk).

“State Enforcement of Fair Housing Policy: A National Comparative Analysis,” Research Blitz: Public Policy in the American States, Midwest Political Science Association Conference, Chicago, IL, April 10, 2016 (with Eric M. Wilk).

“Race and Fair Housing Enforcement in the South and Non-South,” Panel on Civil Rights 50 Years Later, Southern Political Science Association Conference, New Orleans, LA, January 16, 2015 (with Eric M. Wilk).

“Race, Segregation, and Housing in America,” Panel on The Politics of Minority Empowerment in Urban America,” American Political Science Association Conference, Washington, DC, August 30, 2014.

“Presidential Rhetoric and Bureaucratic Enforcement,” Panel on Presidential Leadership and White House Operations, American Political Science Association Conference, Chicago, IL, August 31, 2013 (with Joshua Boston and Harvey D. Palmer).

“Enforcing Federal Civil Rights Legislation at the State and Local Levels: Comparing Outcomes in Housing Discrimination Complaints,” Panel on Housing Policy, Midwest Political Science Association Conference, Chicago, IL, April 14, 2012 (with Eric M. Wilk).

“The Right to Fair Housing: Its Development, Growth, and Enforcement,” Panel on Federalism and the Politics of Rights, American Political Science Association Conference, Seattle, WA, September 2, 2011 (with Eric M. Wilk and Nicholas R. Seabrook).

Fair Housing Policy Making in the Lower Federal Courts,” Panel on U.S. Court of Appeals Decision Making, American Political Science Association Conference, Washington, DC, September 5, 2010 (with Nicholas R. Seabrook and Eric M. Wilk).

Related Professional Activity (selected since 2010)

Chair, Panel on Executive Power and Democratic Functioning in the Trump Era, American Political Science Association Conference, Boston, MA, August 31, 2018.

Chair, Panel on Inequality and Public Policy, Midwest Political Science Association Conference, Chicago, IL, April 6, 2017.

Chair, Panel on State Constitutions and Courts, Midwest Political Science Association Conference, Chicago, IL, April 9, 2016.

Chair, Panel on Empirical Studies of Trial Courts, Midwest Political Science Association Conference, Chicago, IL, April 18, 2015.

Chair and Discussant, Panel on Courts and Federalism, Midwest Political Science Association Conference, Chicago, IL, April 4, 2014.

Chair, Panel on Race, Segregation, and Education, American Political Science Association Conference, Chicago, IL, August 30, 2013.

Chair and Discussant, Panel on Inequities and Resource Distribution in U.S. Social Policies, Midwest Political Science Association Conference, Chicago, IL, April 14, 2012.

Chair, Panel on Process and Procedure in the Federal Courts, Midwest Political Science Association Conference, Chicago, IL, April 2, 2011.

Chair and Discussant, Panel on Constitutional Conflicts, Northeastern Political Science Association Conference, Boston, MA, November 11, 2010.

Memberships (Past and Present)

American Political Science Association

Law and Society Association

Midwest Political Science Association

New England Political Science Association

New York State Political Science Association

Northeastern Political Science Association

Policy Studies Organization

Southern Political Science Association

Grants, Honors, Awards (selected)

Listed in Who’s Who in America, Marquis Who’s Who, 2003-present

Lifetime Achievement Award, Who’s Who in America, Marquis Who’s Who, 2018   

Grants, Baldy Center for Law and Social Policy, University at Buffalo, 1995-2018

Listed in Who’s Who in the World, Marquis Who’s Who, 2003-2004, 2009-2016

Grants, Faculty Development, New York State/UUP, 1990-91, 2003-2005, 2009-2012

Strickland Teacher, Middle Tennessee State University, 2011

Lucius Barker Award for the Best Paper Investigating Race or Ethnicity and Politics, 2008

Midwest Political Science Association Conference. Award presented in 2009

Grant, John F. Kennedy Foundation, Boston, MA, 2007

Grant, Dwight D. Eisenhower Foundation, Abilene, KS, 2007

Grant, Truman Library Institute, Independence, MO, 2007

Listed in Who's Who in American Education, Marquis Who's Who, 2004-2007

Grant, Gerald R. Ford Foundation, Ann Arbor, MI, 1997

Grant, Lyndon Baines Johnson Foundation, University of Texas, Austin, TX, 1996

Grant, Bentley Historical Library, University of Michigan, Ann Arbor, MI, 1996

Distinguished Visiting Associate Professor, Robert M. LaFollette Institute of Public Affairs, University of Wisconsin-Madison, 1990-1991

Grant, Robert M. La Follette Institute of Public Affairs, University of Wisconsin-Madison, 1991 Grant, SUNY Research Foundation, 1988-1990

Listed in Who's Who in Emerging Leaders in America, Marquis Who's Who, 1987-1988

President, New York State Political Science Association, 1985-1986

Vice President and Program Chair, New York Political Science Association, 1984-1985

Choice Outstanding Academic Book Award for Supreme Court Activism and Restraint (1982). Award presented in 1983

Grant, SUNY Research Foundation, 1982

Listed in Who’s Who in the East, Marquis Who’s Who, 1981-1982

Grant, National Science Foundation, 1974-1975 (supporting investigator)

Grant, Office of Technology Assessment, U.S. Congress, 1974-1975 (supporting investigator)

Graduate Teaching Assistantships, 1970-1973

National Defense Education Act Fellowship, 1967-1970

Pi Sigma Alpha; Pi Gamma Mu; Pi Sigma Beta

C. C. Sims Award, 1967 (most outstanding political science major)

Who's Who Among Students in American Universities and Colleges, 1967

Scholarship and Dean’s List, Undergraduate School, 1963-1967

University Service (selected)

Member, Buffalo Seminar on Racial Justice, Baldy Center for Law and Social Policy, 2005-2018

Member, Faculty Senate, 2005-2007; Alternate, Spring 2005, Fall 2007, Spring 2008

Member, Committee on Law and Social Justice, Civic Engagement and Public Policy, UB2020, 2006

Co-Founder and Member, Fair Housing and Homelessness Working Group, Baldy Center for Law and Social Policy, 1988-1990

Member, Faculty of Social Sciences Policy Committee, 1989-1990

Member, Faculty Senate Standing Committee on the Bylaws, 1982-1985

Member, Faculty Senate Standing Committee on Tenure and Privileges, 1982-1984

Departmental Service (selected)

Pre-Law Adviser, 1978-2017

Director, Undergraduate Studies, 1987

Director, New York State Legislative Internship Program, 1991-1992

Chair, Public Law Ph.D. Comprehensive Field Examination Committee, 2003-2005, 2007-2011, 2013-2014, 2016-2018; Member 2003-2018

Chair, Public Policy Ph.D. Comprehensive Field Examination Committee, 1995-1996, 1999-2000, 2002-2003; Member, 1981-1982, 1986-1987, 1993-1996, 1999-2003

Chair, American Politics Ph.D. Comprehensive Field Examination Committee, 1984, 1989; Member 1982-1984, 1989, 1992-1993, 1995

Chair, Undergraduate Studies Committee, 1987; Member, 1979-1980, 1981-1982, 1986-1987, 1998-2008, 2015

Chair, Public Law Search Committee, 2013-2014, Member, 2005-2009, 2013-2014

Member, Graduate Studies Committee, 1977-1978, 1981-1982, 1985-1986, 1988-1989, 2012-2013

Member, Advisory Committee, 1980-1982, 1987, 1989-1990, 2011-2012, 2014-2015

Member, Personnel and Tenure Committee, 1979-1980, 1981-1982, 1992-1993

Dissertation Committees (since 2009)

Adam Nye, chair, Ph.D. awarded 2009

Nicholas Seabrook, member, Ph.D. awarded 2010

Justin DePlato, member, Ph.D. awarded 2012

Kristen Ng, member, Ph. D. awarded 2013

Dylan McLean, member, Ph.D. awarded 2015

Tasha Lavey, member, Ph.D. awarded 2016

Ben Carlson, chair, Ph.D. awarded 2016

Jenny Kahl, chair, Ph.D. awarded 2017

Elizabeth Tillman, member, Ph.D. awarded 2018

Courses Taught

Introduction to American Politics (undergraduate)

Issues in Contemporary Politics (undergraduate)

Law and the Political Process (undergraduate)

Cases in Civil Liberties (undergraduate)

Protecting Civil Liberties (undergraduate)

Constitutional Law (undergraduate)

Judicial Politics (undergraduate)

Public Policy Making (undergraduate)

Politics of Housing (undergraduate)

Advanced Civil Liberties (undergraduate)

Advanced Constitutional Law (undergraduate)

Policy Making Process (graduate)

Constitutional Law (graduate)

Constitutional Law II (graduate)

Judicial Process (graduate)

Public Policy Problems (graduate)

Implementing Civil Rights Policy (graduate)

American Political Frontiers (graduate)













over 1 year ago
Hi Professor Lamb, Thank you so much for your submission. I will let our board of editors know.
Alejandra Chumbes – over 1 year ago
login to leave comment